Voices that are not: The Problems of the Pseudohallucination Concept

Alvaro Cavieres, Pablo López-Silva

ABSTRACT


The term pseudohallucination was originally introduced to characterize hallucinatory phenomena not exhibiting the paradigmatic features of hallucinations. In our context, and directly following Jaspers’ description, the term has been used to characterize a specific type of auditory hallucination in schizophrenic patients i.e. the so-called voices. However, this formation is not shared in other contexts. This paper suggests that Jaspers’ formulation is inexact and problematic when trying to describe the semiology, philosophical foundations, and aetiology of the phenomenon. In addition, we claim that this lack of etiological and nosological clarity lead to serious doubts about the real utility of the use of the term within current descriptive psychopathology. We conclude by proposing two potential alternatives that the use of the term might have within the field.

Keywords: Hallucinations; Pseudohallucinations; Jaspers; Voices; Schizophrenia

Pseudohallucination: A Problematic Tradition


A review of the current situation of descriptive psychopathology reveals that: (i) many terms historically coined by it are not longer in use, (ii) other terms, although in use, reproduce philosophical, empirical and phenomenological problems, and, finally, (iii) few new concepts have been clearly incorporated into the field1. All this inevitably leads us to ask ourselves about the real usefulness of current descriptive psychopathology, understood as a kind of language and as a tool in the diagnosis and treatment of clinical entities.

As pointed out by Berrios and Olivares  1, to acquire a comprehensive understanding of psychopathological phenomena, professionals in the area need to understand "Why the symptoms were defined in a particular way." Thus, the authors ask, "[were] they dictated by the inevitable reality of the phenomenon?" or "Were they the result of a theoretical commitment that is no longer relevant to us?" (p.153). Thus, recalibrating descriptive psychopathology requires considering the history of the terms it uses to designate brain symptoms, behaviors, and disorders, and then an in-depth discussion of the theoretical concepts underlying the field; all this accompanied by careful clinical observation of the phenomenon sought to be understood 2,3,4,5.

The term pseudohallucination was originally introduced to designate any hallucinatory phenomenon present in the subject's field of consciousness that did not exhibit all the paradigmatic characteristics of hallucinations. Among other aspects, hallucinations with sensory richness, insight or projection in the subjective internal space were included in this category 6,7,8. As Berrios 2indicates, the use of the term historically emerges as a succession of dichotomous questions: perception or imagination?, voluntary or involuntary?, internal or external space?, a sensory or multiple modality?, continuous or discontinuous with normality?, mild or intense?, with or without insight?, among others.

Now, in our field, and directly following the description of Jaspers9, the term pseudohallucination has been used to refer to a specific type of auditory hallucinations present in people with schizophrenia: the voices, assigning it a special semiological value10. However, this diagnostic tradition is not shared by other contexts. For example, the term is completely absent in the CIE-1011 and the DSM-512. Indeed, the latter describes the voices simply as hallucinations, that is, "experiences similar in strength and impact to perception, but without external stimuli."

Towards a History of Pseudohallucinations


Friedrich Hagen13 used the term pseudohallucination for the first time to refer to the hallucinations that occur in undiagnosed subjects who remain aware of their abnormalityi . Nevertheless, the same author acknowledges that he is continuing a debate of the French School starring, among others, Esquirol, Baillager and Michéa2. Later, the concept is used by Kandisky14, who, based on his own psychotic experiences, describes a pathological manifestation of memory and fantasy with full sensory richness, intrusive and received with a feeling of passivity, thus differentiating it from true hallucinations.ii.

Lugaro15 states that pseudohallucinations are pure and egodistonic representations present in chronic psychotic states such as schizophrenia and that they can cause secondary delusionsiii. Furthermore, it suggests that, unlike hallucinations --which would result from irritation of perceptual centers --pseudohallucinations would originate in associative centers. Apparently, Lugaro was trying to reach a clearer delimitation of the concept of psychic hallucinations, previously introduced by Baillarge16. The latter distinguished between psychosensory hallucinations (produced by the involuntary activation of the imagination and memory, the suppression of external sensations and the internal arousal of the senses), and psychic hallucinations (in which the sensoriality was weak or non-existent, since it did not there was participation of the sensory apparatus).

All these proposals place the explanatory emphasis on the sensory aspects of the phenomenon. Breaking this trend, Seglas17 tries to explain pseudohallucinations as the exacerbation of the internal verbalization of thought (internal language) or hyperendophasia, which, having clarity and sensory precision, becomes unknown to the subject, although lacking external projection. Seglas calls these internal voices verbal pseudohallucinations due to their origin, in which different degrees of motor activation can be found in addition to the auditory component.

One of the greatest milestones in the history of the concept occurs when Jaspers --in his General Psychopathology9 --establishes a sharp separation between hallucinations and pseudohallucinations. While hallucinations are disturbances of the perception of external objective reality, pseudohallucinations are special forms of imagination or representations (p. 89). From this, it follows that hallucinations are corporeal, objective, and projected in external space, while the latter are imaginary, subjective, and appear in the internal field. Furthermore, perceptions are complete, sensory rich, easily retained, and independent of the subject's will. However, it is important to point out that, according to Jaspers, what separates perception of representation "always without transition... through an abyss," are the corporeality and exteriority of the former, "representations can successively acquire all the other characters that have been attributed to perceptions."

Jaspers' description will be incorporated in the most important psychopathology texts in our environment 10, where it is given a fundamental semiological importance, since it is stated that "there is no perception of voices inside the head" and then "most of the sensory-perceptual disorders of psychiatric patients correspond to pseudohallucinations, and only a tiny minority present true hallucinations" (p. 56). Now, despite the historical weight that this use has in local descriptive psychopathology, here we want to suggest that the term does not offer any guidance regarding the origin of the voices in schizophrenia, ,nor, as we will see below, does it fit all the clinical descriptions of the phenomenon.

i.- According to the use of Hagen, pseudo-hallucinations would become a dimension of the hallucinatory phenomenon.

ii.- Main difference with the use of Hagen. See note ii.

iii.- In this way, Lugaro manages to connect perceptual mechanisms with those mechanisms that, in altered states, would be responsible for the creation of delusions. This idea will be fundamental for the development of the current dominant neuropsychiatric theory of delusions (Coltheart & Davies, 2000; Coltheart, 2015).

The Semiology of Voices: Phenomenology and Progression


It is essential to point out that our questioning originates from trying to establish whether the voices heard by people with schizophrenia are hallucinations or pseudohallucinations. In this sense, the discussion is diagnostic and refers to the way in which psychiatrists use phenomenological keys to classify the phenomenon into clinical categories that will guide its diagnosis and treatment. During this section, we will review the most relevant aspects of the voices reported by patients.

Direct clinical observation shows that the voices heard by the patients do not easily fit in the descriptions provided by Jaspers. The phenomenology of voices suggests that they are perceived with different degrees of sensory freshness, objectivity, internal or external projection, and insight 18. A fundamental observation, generally ignored, is that, in the same subject, voices can change according to their clinical state v .

Possibly, one of the best description of the voices is offered by Kraepelin19, who in addition to pointing out their characteristics, registers their changes during the evolution of early dementia. Thus, at the beginning of the disease, patients tend to hear "simple noises, cracking, buzzing, ringing in the ears, ringing of bells, blows, table shifts, crackling whips, trumpets, Tyrolean songs, other songs, cries of children, bird whistles, explosions, chirps" (p. 33). Later, when the condition progresses:

The symptom peculiar to early dementia--namely, hearing voices---develops gradually or suddenly. Sometimes, they are whispers. Sometimes, they are loud or suppressed. It is not uncommon for illusions to be connected with real noises: the clock speaks, the running of the water is transformed into words. Voices are often related to hearing: voices entered through one ear and exited through the other. But it is especially characteristic of early dementia that the patient's own thoughts appear to him spoken aloud. (p.33-34)

Also Jaspers9 records the presence in acute psychosis of "melodies, noises and machine grinding […]" and "both here, and in chronic psychoses, voices, the invisible ones that often shout to patients as much as possible" appear (p. 95). But in turn, he warns that, "it is necessary to distinguish the pseudohallucinations from the authentic voices" (p. 96) and gives a description in which both would be present in the same subject when he points out that:

A chronic paranoid distinguished a direct speaking of voices from outside by walls and tubes, from direct speaking in which his pursuers forced him to hear something internally, but in which those internal voices were not located outside nor were they corporeal (p.96).

Recent studies reflect a wide heterogeneity in the descriptions of voices made by patients, questioning the conditions offered by Jaspers to distinguish between hallucinations and pseudohallucinations. While some refer to a clarity similar to a conversation with another person20 others report it as ideas or 'silent sensations'21,22. The majority can differentiate them from their own20,23 thoughts and, generally, have a normal volume. Whispers and screams are less frequent, and in general, the voices are referred to as both inside and outside the head21,22. Although many patients hear more than one voice, most report a middle-aged male voice that gives orders or insults, but can also make positive comments [24].

Through an statistical analysis, Stephane et al25, conclude that voices in people with schizophrenia can be organized in two clusters: (i) the first, with low linguistic complexity, repetitive content, attributed to itself, located in the external objective space and associated with control strategies, and (ii) a second one, with high linguistic complexity, systematized content, multiple voices, attributed to others, and located in the internal subjective space.

McCarty-Jones and their collaborators26 built another classification system consisting of four groups: (i) voices as such, constant comments and orders, repetitive, in the first or third person, and internal, (ii) own thinking, in the first person that do not address the subject, and with characteristics similar to memory, (iii) non-verbal hallucinations, described as meaningless noises, and (iv) reproductions, or phenomena identical to the memory of someone speaking.

Finally, another study describes the evolution of hallucinatory symptoms, in a population of subjects at high risk of psychosis27. The contents become progressively clearer and more persecutory, and in turn, the feeling of listening to your own thoughts decreases and the feeling of listening to the voices of others increases, and along with this, progressively less insight and internal projection. In this context, it is reasonable to think that these changes are related to the progression of the neurobiological alteration, or that the voices interact with other subjective dimensions, which ultimately influences the way the experience is reported.

v.- In this context, it is not clear whether the phenomenology of voices itself varies (that is, their phenomenal content) or simply the way in which such experiences are communicated in light of the availability of more informed and rationalized explanatory hypotheses within the explanatory repertoire of the patient. Although the way of reporting an experience can vary, its phenomenal content a posteriori and the clarification of the relationship between these two dimensions of the psychopathological phenomenon remains open to debate.

What to do with the Concept of Pseudohallucinations?


In light of our analysis, the used of the term pseudohallucinations, to refer to voices in schizophrenia presents several problems. First, the current biological understanding of the phenomenon does not allow distinguishing between hallucinations and pseudohallucinations as two separate phenomena, so the use of the term pseudohallucination could be considered unnecessary from a purely naturalistic point of view.

A second problem is that the distinction raised by Jaspers does not seem to apply clearly to voices reported in the first person. In this sense, we believe that any nosological category should respect the way in which the experience is communicated, so that its phenomenological characteristics serve as the main guide for establishing diagnostic distinctions 4. Here, the main issue is that the attributes of the voices phenomenon are gradual and do not make it possible to establish a clear and unambiguous parameter to distinguish hallucinations from pseudohallucinations, so that distinctions, in this sense, would be arbitrary, or worse still, capricious.

On the other hand, on a theoretical and practical level, a sharp separation between representation and perception does not seem sustainable. Such a distinction would imply that pseudohallucinations, as representational states, would be purely cognitive episodes (such as beliefs or judgements), which is not consistent with the phenomenological descriptions of the patients. In other words, where could his sensoriality come from, rather than from a perceptual act, even if it is abnormal.

Jaspers also notes that while hallucinations arise as disturbances in the perception of the external world, pseudohallucinations emerge as special forms of imagination or representation. In addition to the fact that purely cognitive states do not possess the sensory quality reported by patients, there is at least one other problem with this idea, given by the sense of voluntariness i.e. the experience of agency and control regarding the production of certain contents in the mind of a subject.

Given this, we must ask ourselves: what to do with the concept of pseudohallucination? We believe that considering the current problems of using the term in our environment, there are two alternatives available that could guide its reassignment. On the one hand, a radical alternative, which would imply its total abandonment; on the other, a conservative option, which considers its reinterpretation as a phenomenon belonging to a phenomenological and nosological continuum, from which to understand the phenomenon of hallucinations longitudinally.

The radical alternative is attractive, because there is no evidence that the biological alteration of schizophrenia originates differently from two separate phenomena. From this point of view, the term could be abandoned simply on the basis of its undifferentiation. Furthermore, eliminating categories that do not seem to have a well-defined organic origin avoids hindering the conceptual, empirical, and phenomenological delimitation of concepts that do possess a clearer origin, such as hallucinations vi. In this way, all the characteristics that seem to give life to the concept of pseudohallucination could be integrated into the concept of hallucination, allowing a more complex characterization of this concept.

In this way, there would be no place for distinctions between pseudohallucinations and hallucinations, because there is no categorical distinction between and within individuals with schizophrenia. It would seem more plausible to converge the phenomenon, the alteration, and the terms used to refer to voices with a unique term1.

However, radically abandoning a historically inherited category may entail losing some insights that it may contain. Even with its undifferentiation, the concept of pseudo-hallucination could capture relevant information about the phenomenon of voices. But, how to retain the term, with the diverse problems already described?

A conservative alternative offers to maintain the concept of pseudohallucination as part of a phenomenological continuum, to which hallucinations also belong. Recall that the phenomenology of voices examined above shows complexities and variations in all its characteristics. The data suggest the idea that biological causes, could have a severity scale, as evidenced by the fact that voices do not commonly disappear, but rather are modified or integrated into the subject's psyche. From this, it would be possible for hallucinatory voices and pseudo-hallucinatory voices to refer to two categories that would instantiate two evolutionary moments of a continuum.

Recurring again to Berríos46 one of the ideas at the base of this alternative is that the biology related to voices could give rise to different conscious phenomena, depending on the way in which such a causal element is impregnated by other dimensions of the subject, such as, cultural beliefs, psychological resources, states of mind, functioning of executive functions, and prior knowledge, among many others.

vi.- From a philosophical point of view, one could call this strategy eliminitivist, such as the one proposed by Churchland regarding the use of mental concepts.

CONCLUSIONS


The concept of pseudohallucination was originally introduced to designate any hallucinatory phenomenon that arose without fulfilling all the classic characteristics. After a series of conceptual swings, Jaspers introduces the idea that while hallucinations are disturbances in the perception of external objective reality, pseudohallucinations would be special forms of representations. In this way, the hallucinations would have a corporeal, objective nature and would be projected in outer space, while the latter would be imaginary, subjective and would appear in the subject's internal field. In this work, we have suggested that the use of the Jasperian formulation to call the voices of people with schizophrenia pseudo-hallucinations, is highly problematic in our environment, and that there are two alternatives that could guide the future of the term: eliminate its use, or integrate with the concept of hallucination into a phenomenological continuum.

It is important to note that both alternatives have strengths and weaknesses. Our task here has only been to point out both potential paths in order to inform future decisions and discussions regarding the use of the term. On the one hand, the radical alternative must argue that abandoning the term is better than its phenomenological and empirical study. On the other hand, the conservative alternative must justify the use of the concept through the correspondence between the expressed semiological characteristics (e.g. voices of men, one or more voices, internal or external, etc.) and basic biological disturbances, even though there is a dimensional spectrum within the phenomenon of voices. The deepening of these aspects is key to a thorough understanding of the phenomenon of voices.

BIBLIOGRAPHY


  1. Berrios G, Olivares Diez J. Psicopatología Descriptiva: Aspectos Cualitativos y Cuantitativos. Revista de Psicología ( PUCP). 1995;13(2):143-159.
  2. Berrios G. The History of Mental Symptoms : Descriptive Psychopathology since the Nineteenth Century. Cambridge University Press; 1996.
  3. Cooper R. Classifying Madness : A Philosophical Examination of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. New York: Springer; 2005.
  4. López-Silva P. La relevancia filosófica del estudio de la esquizofrenia. Cuestiones metodológicas y conceptuales. Rev Colomb Psiquiatr. 2014;43(3):168-174.
  5. Bolton D. What Is Mental Disorder? : An Essay in Philosophy, Science, and Values. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2008.
  6. Villagrán J, Luque R. Pseudoalucinación:un análisis crítico. Rev Asoc Esp Neuropsiq. 1994;50:391-402.
  7. van der Zwaard R, Polak M. Pseudohallucinations: A pseudoconcept? A review of the validity of the concept, related to associate symptomatology. Compr Psychiatry. 2001;42(1):42-50.
  8. Sanati A Pseudohallucinations: a critical review Dialogues in Philosophy, Mental and Neuro Sciences 5 (2):42-47.
  9. Jaspers K, Saubidet RO, Santillán DA. Psicopatología General. Fondo de Cultura Económica; 1993.
  10. Capponi R. Psicopatología y Semiología Psiquiátrica. Primera Ed. Santiago, Chile: Editorial Universitaria; 1987.
  11. Organización Mundial de la Salud.: CIE-10. Trastornos Mentales y del Comportamiento. Décima Revisión de la Clasificación Internacional de las Enfermedades. Descripciones clínicas y pautas para el diagnóstico. Organización Mundial de la Salud, Ginebra, 1992.
  12. American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders. American Psychiatric Association; 2013.
  13. Hagen F. Zur theorie der hallucination. Allg Z Psychiatr. 1868;25:1-107.
  14. Kokoulina Ekaterina AT. La psicosis del psiquiatra: la vida y obra del Dr. Kandinsky. Rev Asoc Esp Neuropsiq. 2012;32(113):39-53.
  15. Lugaro E. Sulle pseudo-allucinazioni (allucinacione psichiche di Baillager). Contributo a lla psicologia della demenza paranoide. Riv Patol Nerv Ment. 1903;8:1-87.
  16. Baillager J. Physiologie des hallucinations: les deux theories. Ann Med Psychol (Paris). 1886;4:19-39.
  17. Seglas J. Alucinacioness psíquicas y pseudo alucinaciones verbales. J Psychol. 1914:289-315.
  18. McCarthy-Jones S. The phenomenology of heraring voices in people with psychiatric disorders. In: Hearing Voices. The Histories,Causes and Meaning of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press; 2012:101-133.
  19. Kraepelin E. La Demencia Precoz. Buenos Aires: Editorial Polemos; 2008.
  20. Leudar I, Thomas P, McNally D, Glinski A. What voices can do with words: pragmatics of verbal hallucinations. Psychol Med. 1997;27(4):885-898.
  21. Nayani T, David A. The auditory hallucination: a phenomenological survey. Psychol Med. 1996;26(1):177-189.
  22. Moritz S, Larøi F. Differences and similarities in the sensory and cognitive signatures of voice-hearing, intrusions and thoughts. Schizophr Res. 2008;102(1-3):96-107.
  23. Hoffman RE, Varanko M, Gilmore J, Mishara AL. Experiential features used by patients with schizophrenia to differentiate “voices” from ordinary verbal thought. Psychol Med. 2008;38(8):1167-1176..
  24. Garrett M, Silva R. Auditory hallucinations, source monitoring, and the belief that voices are real. Schizophr Bull. 2003;29(3):445-457.
  25. Stephane M, Thuras P, Nasrallah H, Georgopoulos A. The internal structure of the phenomenology of auditory verbal hallucinations. Schizophr Res. 2003;61(2-3):185-193.
  26. McCarthy-Jones S, Trauer T, Mackinnon A, Sims E, Thomas N, Copolov D. A new phenomenological survey of auditory hallucinations: evidence for subtypes and implications for theory and practice. Schizophr Bull. 2014;40(1):231-235..
  27. Marshall C, Lu Y, Lyngberg K, Deighton S, Cadenhead K, Cannon T et al. Changes in symptom content from a clinical high-risk state to conversion to psychosis. Early Interv Psychiatry. August 2017 doi: 10.1111/eip.12473. [Epub ahead of print].
  28. Behrendt R. Underconstrained perception: a theoretical approach to the nature and function of verbal hallucinations. Compr Psychiatry. 39(4):236-248.
  29. Bentall R. The illusion of reality: a review and integration of psychological research on hallucinations. Psychol Bull. 1990;107(1):82-95..
  30. McCarthy-Jones S. Neuroscience and hearing voices: it´s the brain, stupid? In: Hearing Voices. The Histories, Causes and Meaning of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press; 2012:191-222.
  31. Jardri R, Sommer I. Functional Brain Imaging of Hallucinations: Symptom Capture Studies. In: The Neuroscience of Hallucinations. New York, NY: Springer New York; 2013:375-391.
  32. Ford J, Hoffman R. Functional Brain Imaging of Auditory Hallucinations: From Self-Monitoring Deficits to Co-opted Neural Resources. In: The Neuroscience of Hallucinations. New York, NY: Springer New York; 2013:359-373.
  33. Uhlhaas P. Dysconnectivity, large-scale networks and neuronal dynamics in schizophrenia. Curr Opin Neurobiol. 2013;23(2):283-290.
  34. Kasper B, Kasper E, Pauli E, Stefan H. Phenomenology of hallucinations, illusions, and delusions as part of seizure semiology. Epilepsy Behav. 2010;18(1-2):13-23.
  35. von Holst, E., and Mittelstaedt H. Das Reafferenzprinzip. Wechselwirkungen zwischen Zentralnervensystem und Peripherie. Naturwissenschaften. 1950;37:464-476.
  36. Sperry R. Neural basis of the spontaneous optokinetic response produced by visual inversion. J Comp Physiol Psychol. 1950;43:482-489.
  37. Chen C-M, Mathalon D, Roach B, Cavus I, Spencer D, Ford J. The corollary discharge in humans is related to synchronous neural oscillations. J Cogn Neurosci. 2011;23(10):2892-2904..
  38. Ford J, Mathalon D, Kalba S, Whitfield S, Faustman W, Roth W. Cortical responsiveness during talking and listening in schizophrenia: An event-related brain potential study. Biol Psychiatry. 2001;50(7):540-549.
  39. Ford J, Mathalon D. Electrophysiological evidence of corollary discharge dysfunction in schizophrenia during talking and thinking. J Psychiatr Res. 2004;38(1):37-46.
  40. Ford J, Roach B, Faustman W, Mathalon D. Synch before you speak: auditory hallucinations in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry. 2007;164(3):458-466..
  41. Ford J, Mathalon DH, Roach BJ, et al. Neurophysiological evidence of corollary discharge function during vocalization in psychotic patients and their nonpsychotic first-degree relatives. Schizophr Bull. 2013;39(6):1272-1280.
  42. Feinberg I, Guazzelli M. Schizophrenia--a disorder of the corollary discharge systems that integrate the motor systems of thought with the sensory systems of consciousness. Br J Psychiatry. 1999;174:196-204.
  43. Heinks-Maldonado T, Mathalon D, Houde J, Gray M, Faustman W, Ford J. Relationship of imprecise corollary discharge in schizophrenia to auditory hallucinations. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2007;64(3):286-296..
  44. van Swam C, Dierks T, Hubl D. Electrophysiological exploration of hallucinations (EEG,MEG). In: Jardri R, Cachia A, Thomas P, Pins D, eds. The Neuroscience of Hallucinations. New York, NY: Springer New York; 2013:317-342.
  45. McCarthy-Jones S. Neuropsychological models I: inner speech. In: Hearing Voices. The Histories, Causes and Meaning of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press; 2012:223-264.
  46. Berrios G. Formación de sintomas mentales. In: Hacia Una Nueva Epistemología de La Psiquiatría. Buenos Aires: Polemos; 2011:189-199.


HOW TO QUOTE?


(2024). Voices that are not: The Problems of the Pseudohallucination Concept.Journal of Neuroeuropsychiatry, 57(4).
Recovered from https://www.journalofneuropsychiatry.cl/articulo.php?id= 20
2024. « Voices that are not: The Problems of the Pseudohallucination Concept» Journal of Neuroeuropsychiatry, 57(4). https://www.journalofneuropsychiatry.cl/articulo.php?id= 20
(2024). « Voices that are not: The Problems of the Pseudohallucination Concept ». Journal of Neuroeuropsychiatry, 57(4). Available in: https://www.journalofneuropsychiatry.cl/articulo.php?id= 20 ( Accessed: 19abril2024 )
Journal Of Neuropsichiatry of Chile [Internet]. [cited 2024-04-19]; Available from: https://www.journalofneuropsychiatry.cl/articulo.php?id=20

 

DOWNLOAD PDF VERSION